Skip to main content

[]

Intended for healthcare professionals
Skip to main content

Abstract

The claim of liberal constitutionalism is that a text-like object or a ‘diplomatically abstract’ set of principles can work a deflection of disagreements within a pluralist polity. But this project assumes both that pluralism remains amenable to reason and that reason is a capacity independent of the profound differences of meaning, value, and forms of life that shape those disagreements. Neither assumption is correct. Differences in norms, values, and forms of life inevitably undergird and structure differences in meaning, perception, and interpretation. Consequently, a constitution (even when written and accompanied by judicial review) will necessarily unfold in an ongoing process of political cooperation and contestation. Legitimacy can arise only from the practice of democracy itself – that is, self-governance under conditions that realistically accord equal recognition and respect to all participants. Law is not some abstract entity or prior fixation, special and above. It is not, as Michelman once said, ‘an autonomous force’ that provides ‘an external untouchable rule of the game’. It is just another social institution or performative practice that does (or does not) reflect our democratic nomos. To be committed, as a strong democrat, to the rule of law is to be committed to the idea that we make the rules by which we govern ourselves. Equal voice, equal power, and equal law are just self-government. They are internal to – that is, constitutive of – the game. They are not untouchable; indeed, they are being manhandled every day. But they nevertheless describe a democratic constitution that fully legitimates itself in its performance.

Get full access to this article

View all access and purchase options for this article.

References

Aeschylus. 1975. The Suppliants, Janet Lembke Trans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Aeschylus. 2020 The Suppliants, E. D. A. Morshead trans: GlobalGrey.
Arendt Hannah. 1965. On Revolution. London & New York: Penguin Books.
Aristotle. 1984. The Athenian Constitution, P. J. Rhodes Trans. London & New York: Penguin Classics.
Barber Benjamin. 1996. “Misreading Democracy.” In Dēmokratia: A Conversation on Democracies Ancient and Modern, edited by Josiah Ober, Hedrick Charles. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Brest Paul. 1980. “The Misconceived Quest for the Original Understanding.” Boston University Law Review 60: 204–38.
Cohen Morris R. 1927. “Property and Sovereignty.” Cornell Law Quarterly 13: 8–30.
Cover Robert M. 1975. Justice Accused: Antislavery and the Judicial Process. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Cover Robert M. 1983. “The Supreme Court, 1982 Term – Foreword: Nomos and Narrative.” Harvard Law Review 97: 4–68.
Deutsch Jan G. 1968. “Neutrality, Legitimacy, and the Supreme Court: Some Intersections between Law and Political Science.” Stanford Law Review 20: 169–261.
Ehrenberg Victor. 1950. “Origins of Democracy.” Historia: Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 1: 515–548.
Ely John Hart. 1980. Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Euben J. Peter. 1996. “Reading Democracy: ‘Socratic’ Dialogues and the Political Education of Democratic Citizens.” In Dēmokratia: A Conversation on Democracies Ancient and Modern, edited by Ober Josiah, Hedrick Charles. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Ferrara Alessandro, Michelman Frank I. 2021. Legitimation by Constitution: A Dialogue on Political Liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hale Robert. 1920. “Law Making by Unofficial Minorities.” Columbia Law Review 20: 451–56.
Hale Robert. 1923. “Coercion and Distribution in a Supposedly Non-Coercive State.” Political Science Quarterly 38: 470–94.
Hand Learned. 1958. The Bill of Rights. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Harrington James. 1992. The Commonwealth of Oceana and a System of Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hirschman Albert O. 1970. Exit, Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations, and States. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jefferson Thomas. 1979. “To James Madison from Thomas Jefferson, 6 September 1789,” the Papers of James Madison, Vol. 12, 2 March 1789 – 20 January 1790 and Supplement 24 October 1775 – 24 January 1789, Hobson Charles F., Rutland Robert A. eds Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, available online at: Founders Online, National Archives, https://founders.archives.gov/documents/Madison/01-12-02-0248
Kennedy Duncan. 1976. “Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication.” Harvard Law Review 89: 1685–1778.
Kennedy Duncan. 1997. A Critique of Adjudication {fin de siècle}. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Llewellyn Karl. 1934. “The Constitution as an Institution.” Columbia Law Review 34: 1–40.
Merleau-Ponty Maurice. 1962. The Phenomenology of Perception, Colin Smith trans. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Merleau-Ponty Maurice. 1964. Sense and Non-sense. H. Dreyfus and P. Dreyfus trans. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Michelman Frank I. 2022. Constitutional Essentials: On the Constitutional Theory of Political Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press.
Michelman Frank I. 1988. “Law’s Republic.” Yale Law Journal 97: 1493–1537.
Michelman Frank I. 2003. “Ida’s Way: Constructing the Respect-worthy Governmental System.” Fordham Law Review 72: 345–65.
Michelman Frank I. 1967. “Property, Utility, and Fairness: Comments on the Ethical Foundations of ‘Just Compensation’ Law.” Harvard Law Review 80: 1165–1258.
Michelman Frank I. 1999. Brennan and Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Olsen Frances E. 1983. “The Family and the Market: A Study of Ideology and Legal Reform.” Harvard Law Review 96: 1497–1578.
Ostwald Martin. 1969. Nomos and the Beginnings of the Athenian Democracy. London: Clarendon Press.
Ostwald Martin. 1986. From Popular Sovereignty to the Sovereignty of Law: Law, Society, and Politics in Fifth-Century Athens. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Plato. 2009. Protagoras. New York: Oxford University Press.
Plato. 1956. The Great Dialogues of Plato, W. H. D. Rouse trans. New York: Mentor Books.
Post Robert. 2005. “Democracy and Equality.” Journal of Law, Culture and Humanities 1: 142–53.
Vlastos Gregory. 1995. Studies in Greek Philosophy – Volume I: The Presocratics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Whiteside Kerry H. 1988. Merleau-Ponty and the Foundation of an Existential Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Winter Steven L. 1988. “The Metaphor of Standing and the Problem of Self-Governance.” Stanford Law Review 40: 1371–1516.
Winter Steven L. 1990. “Indeterminacy and Incommensurability in Constitutional Law.” California Law Review 78: 1441–1541.
Winter Steven L. 2001. A Clearing in the Forest: Law, Life, and Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Winter Steven L. 2012a. “Down Freedom’s Main Line.” Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 41: 202–14.
Winter Steven L. 2012b. “Freedom’s History in the Making: A Reply.” Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 41: 294–306.
Winter Steven L. 2013. “Frame Semantics and the ‘Internal Point of View.” In Current Legal Issues Colloquium: Law and Language, edited by Freeman Michael, Smith Fiona. London: Oxford University Press.
Winter Steven L. 2019. “What a Vote Is Worth.” Journal of Law in Society 19: 264–72.
Winter Steven L. 2022a. “Bridges of Law, Ideology, and Commitment.” Touro Law Review 37: 1981–2010.
Winter Steven L. 2022b. “‘Who’ or ‘What’ is the Rule of Law?” Philosophy and Social Criticism 47: 655–74.
Winter Steven L. 2023. “The Made and the Made-Up.” Philosophy and Social Criticism 49: 631–49.

Cases

303 Creative LLC v. Elenis, 600 U.S. ___, 143 S. Ct. 2298 (2023).
Cooper v. Dasher, 290 U.S. 106 (1933).
Culombe v. Connecticut, 367 U.S. 568 (1961).
Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, 597 U.S. ___, 142 S. Ct. 2228 (2022).
McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316 (1819).
Monaco v. Mississippi, 292 U.S. 313 (1934).
Morse v. Frederick, 551 U.S. 393 (2007).
Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438 (1928).
Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992).
Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
Rucho v. Common Cause, 588 U.S. ___, 139 S. Ct. 2484 (2019).
Towne v. Eisner, 245 U.S. 418 (1918).
United States v. Carolene Products, 308 U.S. 144 (1938).

Cite article

Cite article

Cite article

OR

Download to reference manager

If you have citation software installed, you can download article citation data to the citation manager of your choice

Share options

Share

Share this article

Share with email
Email Article Link
Share on social media

Share access to this article

Sharing links are not relevant where the article is open access and not available if you do not have a subscription.

For more information view the Sage Journals article sharing page.

Information, rights and permissions

Information

Published In

Article first published online: July 23, 2024
Issue published: September 2024

Keywords

  1. democracy
  2. constitutionalism
  3. legitimacy
  4. reason
  5. nomos

Rights and permissions

© The Author(s) 2024.
Request permissions for this article.

Authors

Affiliations

Notes

Steven L Winter, Wayne State University Law School, 471 West Palmer, Detroit, MI 48230, USA. Email: [email protected]

Metrics and citations

Metrics

Journals metrics

This article was published in Philosophy & Social Criticism.

View All Journal Metrics

Article usage*

Total views and downloads: 97

*Article usage tracking started in December 2016


Articles citing this one

Receive email alerts when this article is cited

Web of Science: 0

Crossref: 1

Figures and tables

Figures & Media

Tables

View Options

Access options

If you have access to journal content via a personal subscription, university, library, employer or society, select from the options below:


Alternatively, view purchase options below:

Purchase 24 hour online access to view and download content.

Access journal content via a DeepDyve subscription or find out more about this option.

View options

PDF/EPUB

View PDF/EPUB

Full Text

View Full Text